For instance, Stephen Davies (“John Cage’s Other philosophers have focused on the distinction between natural and musical sounds, or, more generally, non-musical and musical sounds. Conflating the former with the latter gives rise to the mistaken assumption that emotional descriptions of music must refer to an actual emotional state either in the listener or perhaps in the composer.The field of musical ontology is largely a reflection of debates in general ontology, although some issues are peculiar to the musical case. Music For Youtube, Commercial Music. In particular, she claims that Davies is mistaken in holding that emotional contagion is the result of a listener’s experience of musical expressiveness (392). Jazz standards, it would seem, cannot be located in the way works in the classical tradition can. Dodd takes this objection to conflate the psychological notion of creativity with the metaphysical claim that something is created by composers. It was founded in 2005 by Gualtiero Piccinini, and has been administered by John Schwenkler since late 2011.This blog is all about New ideas in philosophy, psychology, neuroscience from a leading forum for philosophy & science of mind. Lay people are inclined to confuse conceptually (if not phenomenologically) the emotions While the previous section distinguishes the music’s emotional expressiveness from emotional arousal, an elegant view describes the former as an instance of the latter. Dodd’s suggestion is that It then remains to be seen how they justify the listener’s toleration of, or even attraction to, deeply sad music, if such music has the disposition to arouse in them the negative emotional states it expresses.
Much like the children in the story, philosophers of art have tried to do exactly what Kivy said wasn’t advisable, that is, show that music may be profound. Broadly construed, this tradition holds that pieces of music ought to be performed in a way sensitive to the period in which they were composed. John and Ken explore what philosophy has to tell us about music – and vice versa – with Peter Kivy from Rutgers University, author of John and Ken begin by trying to pin down an exact definition for music. His suggestion is that in addition to the capacity music has to allow us to escape our daily concerns regarding the actual world, there is a particularly welcome feature to the alternative world music opens to us. For instance, suppose I write a piece of music for guitar this afternoon. Emotional descriptions of music work in a similar way. His strategy is to appeal to the secondary meaning taken by emotion terms when they are used to describe the outward manifestations of emotions. According to him, the experience of musical expression centrally involves imagination, although it may do so in different ways. Challenge your kids with plenty of solitude so that they can learn to enjoy their own company, to conduct inner dialogues. This move is necessary because, regardless of how optimistic one may be with regard to the value of musical expressiveness, one will be forced to admit that much great music is lacking in expressive power. Against the worry that he may give too prominent a role to the listener’s recognition of the music’s expressive character, he replies that he does not rule out what he calls “non-attentional contagion,” that is, the unconscious, emotional attuning to expressive features of the environment. Consider the case of rock music: the main focus is often the record as opposed to the live performance of the piece, which is arguably the critical focus in the Western classical tradition. Kivy’s solution is to assume that some musical features acquire their expressive character by convention (A historical note: the intuition that the music’s expressive power lies in its resemblance to human expressive behaviour is an old one and can be traced back to Plato. Listening to music expressive of negative emotions is one such activity: one of the ways in which we listen to music with understanding is by reacting emotionally to its expressive character, such as when we are made cheerful by happy music or sad by sad music. Florida, United States About Blog The Brains blog is a leading forum for work in the philosophy and science of mind. Brünnhilde’s Immolation Scene from Götterdämmerung, the final opera in the Ring cycle – video Wagner’s views were shaped by philosophy and ideas in unmatched ways. Peter Kivy points out that a lot of music out there doesn't get listened to anyway! While the view that composers are creative is arguably correct, this view is simply expressing the idea that composers are engaging in a creative process, not that they are bringing something into existence. That we would refuse to do so counts against Davies’ view of profundity (Kivy, “Another Go” 407).According to Dodd, Kivy is right in holding music incapable of communicating propositional content, but he is mistaken in considering this a requirement for profundity. Historically loaded characterisations of musical work’s fundamental ontological nature are often paired with authenticity requirements that include the means of production of a musical structure (for example instrumentation, as in Levinson’s case), whereas fundamental ontologies of a platonic sort tend to set the bar low, in that parameters such as timbre or instrumentation are irrelevant to the instantiation of a musical work.Music isn’t simply sounds we hear. He observes how many human activities that are valuable and sought after possess an intrinsically unpleasant or painful element—think of weight training or running. First, we would consider two pieces identical in their sound structure but composed at different times to be two different pieces.